CHAPTERS
1. On a New List of Categories
2. Questions Concerning Certain Faculties Claimed for Man
3. Some Consequences of Four Incapacities
4. Grounds of Validity of the Laws of Logic
5. Fraser's The Works of George Berkeley
6. On a New Class of Observations, suggested by the priniciples of Logic
7. The Fixation of Belief
8. How to Make Our Ideas Clear
9. The Doctrine of Chances
10. The Probability of Induction
11. The Order of Nature
12. Deduction, Induction, and Hypothesis
13. [from] On the Algebra of Logic
14. Introductory Lecture on the Study of Logic
15. Design and Chance
16. [from] On the Algebra of Logic: A Contribution to the Philosophy of Notation
17. An American Plato: Review of Royce's Religious Aspect of Philosophy
18. One, Two, Three: Kantian Categories
19. A Guess at the Riddle
20. Trichotomic
21. The Architecture of Theories
22. The Doctrine of Necessity Examined
23. The Law of MInd
24. Man's Glassy Essence
25. Evolutionary Love
EP Main Page
EP 1
EP 2
Links
Home


1. On a New List of Categories

P 32: Proceedings of the American Academy of Arts and Sciences 7 (1868):287-98. [Also published in W2:49-9 (with the four other papers in the so-called PAAAS Series and with references to related manuscripts published in W1) and in CP1.545-59. Peirce completely rewrote the paper to serve as the opening chapter of his 1894 "How to Reason" (MS 403).] Presented to the Academy on 14 May 1867, this paper is, according to Peirce, "perhaps the least unsatisfactory, from a logical point of view, that I ever succeeded in producing" and, with item 3 below, one of his two "strongest philosophical works." The culmination of a ten-year effort and the keystone of Peirce's system of philosophy, it argues for a new post-Kantian set of categories (or univeral conceptions) by demonstrating that they are required for the unification of experience. Peirce's argument is essentially a logical derivation, though it depends on a type of mental separation he called 'prescision,' which is also required for his later phenomenological derivation of the categories.

Top




2. Questions Concerning Certain Faculties Claimed for Man

P 26: Journal of Speculative Philosophy 2 (1868):103-14. [Also published in W2:193-211 (with related letters and earlier attempts at this article and the two that follow) and in CP 5.213-63.] Item 2 is the first of three articles usually referred to as the JSP Cognition Series, in which Peirce develops some of the results and consequences of item 1 and attempts "to prove and to trace the consequences of certain propositions in epistemology tending toward the recognition of the reality of continuity and of generality and going to show the absurdity of individualism and of egoism. " (In "The Law of Mind" [item 23], he indicates that this is an early attempt at developing his doctrine of synechism.) Peirce's opposition to Cartesianism results in the following four denials: (1) we have no power of introspection, but all knowledge of the internal world is derived by hypothetical reasoning from our knowledge of external facts, (2) we have no power of intuition, but every cognition is determined logically by previous cognitions, (3) we have no power of thinking without signs, and (4) we have no conception of the absolutely incognizable.

Top




3. Some Consequences of Four Incapacities

P 27: Journal of Speculative Philosophy 2 (1868):140-57. [Also published in W2:211-42 and in CP 5.264-317.] With item 1 above, one of Peirce's two "strongest philosophical works," this article develops an account of mind and reality from the ground prepared in item 2. Peirce asserts that all mental events are valid inferences, and claims that as every thought is a sign, so man himself is a sign. He also gives a fairly detailed account of his theory of signs as of 1868, and makes his first published declaration for scholastic realism. (Peirce's philosophy of mind as developed here is, according to Christopher Hookway, a type of functionalism.)

Top


4. Grounds of Validity of the Laws of Logic: Further Consequences of Four Incapacities

P 41: Journal of Speculative Philosophy 2 (1869):193-208. [Also published in W2:242-72 and in CP 5.318-57. Changes in an offprint (MS 593), prepared as essay 6 of his 1893 "Search for a Method," are recorded in the Notes.] In this article, the culmination of the Cognition Series, Peirce works out a rationale for the objective validity of the laws of logic and, by linking epistemology with a social theory of logic, grounds induction in altruistic sentiments. He also discusses a version of the liar paradox and offers a solution based on the supposition that "every proposition asserts its own truth, " and he makes his first published reference to De Morgan's work on the logic of relations.

Top


5. Fraser's The Works of George Berkeley

P 60: North American Review 113 (October 1871):449-72. [Also published in W2:462-87 (with Chauncey Wright's criticism and Peirce's response [pp. 487-90) and in CP 8.7-38.] In what may be the most important of all his reviews, Peirce discusses the realist-nominalist controversy (which he believed to be of fundamental significance for philosophy as well as life) and gives a detailed account of his already slightly modified scholastic realism. Peirce's common-sense account of truth and reality contains important elements of his developing pragmatism.

Top


6. On a New Class of Observations, Suggested by the Principles of Logic

MS 1104. [First published, as MS 311, in W3:235-37.] Written in the summer of 1877, apparently for presentation, this brief paper recommends the observational study of sensations (as Peirce recommended for all sciences, even mathematics). Opposed to the "ordinary" view that "there are ultimate sensations without any general relations between them," Peirce argues that, although we can never completely capture in general descriptions the differences between different sensations, we can "make an indefinite progress toward such a result." But if that is unconvincing, Peirce goes on to say, perhaps we should try a phenomenological approach. Whether there are pure and completely determinate individual sensations is a question that can be dealt with by observational science; "here then," he concludes, "is a whole world of observation, to which we have been systematically blind, simply because of a wrong metaphysical prejudice."

Top


7. The Fixation of Belief

P 107: Popular Science Monthly 12 (November 1877):l-15. [Also published in W3:242-57 (with parts of earlier versions, MSS 187-189 [pp.22-28]) and in CP 5.358-87. Peirce intended to use this paper as essay 8 of his 1893 "Search for a Method," as chapter 5 of his 1894 "How to Reason" (MS 407), and as the first essay in his 1909/10 "Essays on the Reasoning of Science" (MS 334). Substantive changes in these two are recorded in the Notes; for the handwritten sections in MS 407 and the changes taken from an offprint that is no longer extant, see the CP.] This is the first of a series of six papers, collectively titled "Illustrations of the Logic of Science"; at least one more paper was projected, and they were once listed as a forthcoming book in Appleton's International Scientific Series. The objective of the "Illustrations" is "to describe the method of scientific investigation," and they contain, as Peirce later recalled, "the earliest formulation of a method of logical analysis that [I] had had the habit of alluding to as [my] pragmatism,'" or "the tiny seed that under the culture of richer minds, grew into the goodly tree of that same appellation that already begins to afford a comfortable and wholesome lodge for many a soul." In the first paper, he develops his thesis that thought is a form of inquiry, and belief the cessation of doubt, and he emphasizes the self-corrective nature of the scientific method. He further discusses four methods of fixing belief (those of tenacity and of authority, the a priori method, and the method of science) and argues that only the fourth, which alone appeals to an "external permanency," can lead to success in the long run.

Top


8. How to Make Our Ideas Clear

P 119: Popular Science Monthly 12 (January 1878):286-302. [Also published in W3:257-76 and in CP 5.388-410. Peirce intended to use this paper as essay 9 of his 1893 "Search for a Method" and as chapter 16 of his 1894 "How to Reason" (MS 422); the changes in MS 422 are recorded in the Notes.] Written between 13 and 24 September 1877, while Peirce was sailing to Plymouth, England, this paper criticizes Descartes' doctrine of the clearness of ideas and goes on to develop Peirce's own theory, according to which there are three levels or grades of clearness. The theory of meaning associated with the third grade of clearness is represented in the pragmatic maxim (and is sometimes thought of as an operationalist theory). Peirce ends the paper by applying the pragmatic maxim in his examination of the meaning of several conceptions, including 'realism'. (He later thought that his early pragmatism was too nominalistic.)

Top


9. The Doctrine of Chances

P 120: Popular Science Monthly 12 (March 1878):604-15. [Also published in W3:276-89 and in CP 2.645-60. Although the third and fourth "Illustrations" were intended as one paper, the PSM editors published it in two parts in two successive months. In 1893, Peirce retyped the third paper to serve as essay 10 of "Search for a Method" and chapter 18 of "How to Reason" (MS 424) and, in 1910, he wrote several "Notes to C.S.P.'s Third Paper in the Pop. Sci. Monthly. 1878, March" (in MSS 703 and 704); some of the changes in the typescript and one of the notes of 1910 are recorded in the Notes.] In an early discussion of what will later become his synechism, Peirce argues that the assumption of continuity provides a powerful engine for logic, and he develops his theory of probabilities as the science of logic quantitatively treated (or as general logic). To be logical Peirce says, men must not be selfish, for logic requires the identification of one's interests with those of an unlimited community. (Peirce also discusses the probability of a non-repeatable event in a case that Hilary Putnam has named "Peirce's Puzzle.")

Top


10. The Probability of Induction

P 121: Popular Science Monthly 12 (April 1878):705-18. [Also published in W3:290-305 and in CP 2.669-93.] In this paper, Peirce continues to develop his theory of probability and gives rules for calculating the probability of multiple events. He compares the conceptualistic view (which refers probabilities to events) with the materialistic view (which makes probability the ratio of the frequency of favorable cases to all cases) and differentiates chance from probability. He argues for the frequency view (which he held until nearly the turn of the century) and then connects his views on probability with the nature of inductive (or synthetic) reasoning and the problem of induction, for which be considers the need for an appeal to possible worlds.

Top


11. The Order of Nature

P 122: Popular Science Monthly 13 (June 1878):203-17. [Also published in W3:306-22 and in CP 6.395-427.] In the fifth "Illustrations" paper, Peirce argues against Mill's view that the uniformity of nature is the sole warrant for induction and for the theory set out in the preceding paper: that induction should be explained by the doctrine of probabilities (which, as he points out, should pose no problem for religion). He also proclaims, as he did throughout his life, that "the mind of man is strongly adapted to the comprehension of the world," a capacity explained as the result of natural selection and as being fundamental for success in abductive reasoning (or hypothesis). Finally, he turns to some of the cosmological questions that open the line of inquiry that will eventually result in his guess at the riddle of the universe.

Top


12. Deduction, Induction, and Hypothesis

P 123: Popular Science Monthly 13 (August l878):47O-82. [Also published in W3:323-38 and in CP 2.619-44.] Peirce concludes his six "Illustrations" with a discussion of the three kinds of reasoning (deduction, induction, hypothesis) based on the general form of syllogistic argument composed of rule, case, and result. With examples from the history of science, he demonstrates that hypothesis is different from induction proper in that "hypothesis supposes something of a different kind from what we have directly observed, and frequently something which it would be impossible for us to observe directly," while induction only "infers the existence of phenomena such as we have observed in cases which are similar."

Top


13. [from] On the Algebra of Logic (1880)

P 167: American Journal of Mathematics 3 (1880):15-57. [Also published in W4:163-73 (with two earlier versions of part of the first chapter, MSS 350 and 354 [pp. 38-46], and a fragmentary continuation of the whole article, which ends with "to be continued," in MS 371 [pp. 210-11) and in CP 3.154-81. (Three further attempts at a continuation are in W5:107-15.)] This article holds a place of some importance in the history of formal logic and mathematics. In what is published here from the first chapter, Peirce discusses the relationship between thinking and cerebration (or logic and physiology), formulates the theory for his logic of the copula employing statements of inclusion rather than Boolean equations, and places some of his important epistemological conceptions into the context of formal logic. (Item 16 represents the subsequent stage of his development of this part of the algebra of logic and should be read in conjunction with item 13.)

Top


14. Introductory Lecture on the Study of Logic

P 225: Johns Hopkins University Circulars 2:19 (November 1882):11-12. [Also published in W4:378-82, in CP 7.59-76, and in HPPLS 940-44.] In this "Outline of the Remarks made by Prof. C. S. Peirce, at the beginning of his Course, September, 1882," Peirce reflects on the achievements of Darwin (who had died in April) and attributes them mainly to Darwin's method. In describing the lecture to his eldest brother, James Mills, in a 4 October 1882 letter, Peirce said: "I spoke of our time as the age of method and said that the highest honors could no longer be paid to the mere scientific specialist but to those who adapted the methods of one science to the uses of another. That a liberal education so far as it regards the intellect means logic, considered as the method of methods,—the via ad principia methodorum. That the student ought to feel from the beginning to the end of his course, that in whatever lecture room he is, it is logic he is studying." Peirce is now defining his task as applying the methods of logic, especially induction and hypothesis, to philosophy and science.

Top


15. Design and Chance

MS 875. [First published, as MS 494, in W4:544-54.] Written in December 1883/January 1884, this fragmentary manuscript was used for a lecture entitled "Design and Chance," given before the Johns Hopkins University Metaphysical Club on 17 January 1884. Despite its brevity and incompleteness, it represents a major advance in Peirce's progress toward his guess at the riddle of the universe, and it marks the beginning of his evolutionary explanation of the laws of nature (and his architectonic metaphysics detailed in items 21-25). By the hypotheses of absolute chance, habit-taking, and universal evolution, Peirce extends the postulate that "everything is explicable . . . in a general way."

Top


16. [from] On the Algebra of Logic: A Contribution to the Philosophy of Notation

P 296: American Journal of Mathematics 7 (1885):180-202. [Also published in W5:162-90 (with several related manuscripts, MSS 506-508 and 538-539 [pp. 107-16 and 191-220]) and in CP 3.359-403.] This paper, which Peirce first presented (at least in part) at the 14-17 October 1884 meeting of the National Academy of Sciences in Newport, RI, consists of four parts, and it is recognized as a substantial contribution to modern logic and to the philosophy of logic and the theory of notation. In the first part published here, Peirce considers the different kinds of signs required for a fully adequate logic notation, and he concludes that it is necessary to have tokens (conventional or general signs, usually called symbols), indexes (demonstrative signs), and icons (signs of resemblance). This is the first published appearance of the icon-index-symbol trichotomy and Peirce's first application of his theory of signs to his algebraic logic.

Top


17. An American Plato: Review of Royce's Religious Aspect of Philosophy

MS 1369. [Published, as MS 541, in W 5:221-34 and in CP 8.39-54 (without the opening paragraph).] Written for the Popular Science Monthly in the summer of 1885 (but rejected by the editor, E. L. Youmans), this lengthy review is, according to Peirce's 28 October 1885 letter to William James, "something really very good." After praising Royce for his style of reasoning, which is like Plato's, Peirce criticizes his idealism as being too much like Hegel's, whose "capital error . . . which permeates his whole system . . . is that he almost altogether ignores the Outward Clash." Peirce repeats the thesis of item 16, that three kinds of signs are indispensable in all reasoning, and emphasizes that indexes are necessary to refer to individuals: "One such index must enter into every proposition, its function being to designate the subject of discourse." (According to Max Fisch, items 16 and 17 mark an important stage in Peirce's passage from a one-category to a two-category realism.)

Top


18. One, Two, Three: Kantian Categories

MS 897. [First published, as MS 572, in W5:292-94; see also MSS 545, 546, 548, 573, 575, 578, and 582.] Sometime in 1885, it occurred to Peirce that he may have found the key to the secret of the universe, and he wrote to William James on 20 October: "I have something very vast now . . . It is . . . an attempt to explain the laws of nature, to show their general characteristics and to trace them to their origin & predict new laws by the laws of the laws of nature." He then made his famous 'guess': "three elements are active in the world, first, chance; second, law; and third, habit-taking. Such is our guess of the secret of the sphynx." It remained for him to work the details and consequences of this grand hypothesis into a full-fledged theory. The present paper, written in the summer of 1886 for a book to be entitled "One, Two, Three, " is one of several attempts to organize the principal claims needed to support his guess (and is an early version of the first chapter of item 19).

Top


19. A Guess at the Riddle

MS 909. [First published in CP 1.354 (the opening outline), 1.1-2 (the next two paragraphs), 1.355-68 (chapter 1), 1.373 (chapter 3), 1.374-75 and 379-83 (chapter 4; missing are the final sentence of the second paragraph, the third paragraph, and the first half of the fourth paragraph), and 1.385-416 (chapters 5, 6, and 7). An earlier opening page has the title "Notes for a Book, to be entitled 'A Guess at the Riddle,' with a Vignette of the Sphynx below the Title."] Although chapters 2, 8, and 9 are missing (and probably were never written) and chapter 3 is a mere outline, 'A Guess at the Riddle" is perhaps Peirce's greatest and most original contribution to speculative philosophy, and it marks his deliberate turn to architectonic thought. His three categories, which he speculates are isomorphic with the three elements that are active in the universe (chance, law, and habit-taking), serve as the structure for organizing the branches of philosophy and science, and it is clear that he anticipated a complete reorganization of human knowledge around his triad of universal conceptions; for as he wrote, on a variant opening page, "this book, if ever written, as it soon will be if I am in a situation to do it, will be one of the births of time." Although, unfortunately, Peirce never was in such a situation, it is fortunate that many of his major ideas in the "Guess" would soon appear in the papers of the Monist Metaphysical Series (items 21-25).

Top


20. Trichotomic

MS 1600. [Previously unpublished.] Written (probably for oral presentation) in early 1888 shortly after the completion of item 19, this three-page typescript found in one of the thirteen boxes of MS 1600) is a sort of summary of some of the main points of "A Guess at the Riddle." In addition, it includes a discussion of Peirce's categories applied to signs (a topic that had been projected for the unwritten second chapter of the "Guess") and a comparison of his views, on the subject of dramatic expression and the principles of being, with those of the New York playwright and theater manager Steele MacKaye. The title of the paper is one of the alternatives Peirce had considered for his projected "One, Two, Three," which then became "A Guess at the Riddle."

Top


21. The Architecture of Theories

P 439: The Monist 1 January 1891):161-76. [Also published in CP 6.7-34.] This is the first of five papers (although at least one more had been projected, and "The Reply to the Necessitarians" mentioned in the headnote to item 22 should be considered a companion piece to that item) in the Monist Metaphysical Series, in which Peirce fully applied to metaphysical questions the evolutionary philosophy developed in "A Guess at the Riddle." (The chapter on metaphysics in item 19 is a mere outline.) The architectonic approach of the "Guess" is here explained and defended, and Peirce examines a number of conceptions to determine which ones "ought to form the brick and mortar of a philosophical system." He then reviews many of the essential ideas of the "Guess," again using his categories to organize his examination of different sciences and demonstrates that philosophy requires thoroughgoing evolutionism, that mental phenomena fall into three classes feelings, sensations of reaction, and general conceptions), that the fundamental law of mental action is that feelings and ideas tend to spread, and that "the one intelligible theory of the universe is that of objective idealism, that matter is effete mind." Peirce concludes that chance and continuity are two of the most fundamental ideas on which to build a philosophical theory that is compatible with modern science.

Top


22. The Doctrine of Necessity Examined

P 474: The Monist 2 (April 1892):321-37. [Also published in CP 6.35-65; see also the companion piece to this item, Peirce's lengthy "Reply to the Necessitarians" (6.588-618), a reply to two articles published in the July and October 1892 issues by Paul Carus, editor of the Monist.] In this paper, Peirce considers-and then rejects-the main arguments for determinism, and he concludes that an element of absolute chance prevails in the world. He names his anti-necessitarian doctrine 'tychism' and argues that "tychism must give birth to an evolutionary cosmology, in which all the regularities of nature and mind are regarded as products of growth."

Top


23. The Law of Mind

P 477: The Monist 2 (July 1892):533-59. [Also published in CP 6.102-63.] In this paper, Peirce develops his synechism, the doctrine that continuity is "of prime importance in philosophy" and, according to which, the one law of mind is that ideas tend to spread and to affect other ideas but that, in spreading, they lose intensity as they gain generality. From synechism, the doctrines of logical realism, objective idealism, and tychism follow. Peirce also considers continuity from the standpoint of mathematics (with reference to Cantor), and he isolates two fundamental properties of a continuous series: Aristotelicity (every continuum contains its limits) and Kanticity (every continuum is infinitely divisible); applying the former to philosophy, he finds that consciousness essentially occupies time. He also claims that the three principal types of mental action correspond to the three main classes of logical inference.

Top


24. Man's Glassy Essence

P 480: The Monist 3 (October 1892):1-22. [Also published in CP 6.238-71.] In this paper, Peirce applies his synechistic philosophy to the mind-body problem or "the relation between the psychical and physical aspects of a substance." In order to carry out his purpose of developing a philosophy that adequately represents the state of knowledge in the nineteenth century, he discusses at length, and in elaborate technical detail the constitution of matter and the molecular theory of protoplasm. He associates the main physical properties of protoplasm with the three main types of mental action, and he suggests that-as "matter is effete mind," as "physical events are but degraded or undeveloped forms of psychical events," and as "mechanical laws are nothing but acquired habits, like all the regularities of mind"-"the idealist has no need to dread a mechanical theory of life." Peirce ends his paper with a discussion of the life of ideas and the self-consciousness of groups of individuals.

Top


25. Evolutionary Love

P 521: The Monist 3 (January 1893):176-200. [Also published in CP 6.287-317.] In this fifth (and last) Monist paper, Peirce develops his agapism, the doctrine that the law of love is operative in the world. He argues that of the three kinds of evolution (by fortuitous variation, by mechanical necessity, and by creative love) the third is the most fundamental: "Love, recognizing germs of loveliness in the hateful, gradually warms it into lift, and makes it lovely. That is the sort of evolution which every careful student of my essay 'The Law of Mind' must see that synechism calls for." Peirce delivers a polemic against the "gospel of greed" and laments the fact that sentiment seems to have lost favor; sentimentalism, he says, is "the doctrine that great respect should be paid to the natural judgments of the sensible heart," and he entreats his readers "to consider whether to contemn it is not of all blasphemies the most degrading." He compares some of the views expressed here with those of Christianity, and ends with a discussion of the continuity of mind and the caution that we should not overestimate the importance of the individual.

Top